People to go back to (strikethroughs are people I've already been reading):
Leftist critics of renown include A.S. Neill, John Holt, Paulo Freire,
Paul Willis, Herbert Gintis, Ira Shor, Henry Giroux, Peter McLaren,
Jacques Rancière and Noam Chomsky, just to name a few.
Phillip Jackson’s arguably tamer Life in Classrooms
John Taylor Gatto, 30-year veteran of public school teaching in New York
French sociologist Pierre Bourdieu: his ‘reproduction’ theory
Cornelius Castoriadis who combined both Marxist and psychoanalytic
concepts in his extensive writings on ‘imaginary institutions’.
Quotes from this article:
Liberals and conservatives alike resemble Benjamin’s angel of history,
their attention focused on what they perceive to be the present
‘rubble heap’ of education, colored by a nostalgia for a lost Paradise
and by the yearning to ‘awaken the dead and to piece together what has
been smashed’. As they back into the future, they often appear
willfully blind to the concrete historical circumstances of those
whose lives literally depend on schooling, and to the real obstacles
to social justice that the least advantaged persistently face in
becoming educated.
The inequities associated with highly variable funding schemes,
teacher shortages or neighborhood segregation will not be solved by
providing every parent with a voucher or ‘chartering’ urban districts.
The claim that ‘privatization’ is the answer to the problems of our
educational or political systems makes no historical or ethical sense.
In our view, quality schools should be public in the best sense of the
word: free and available to all, everywhere, at the point of entrance;
challenging and appealing to the intrinsic motivation to learn in all
children; and entailing the cultivation of knowledge, dispositions and
competences necessary for preparing young people to engage with the
wider world. We therefore make no common cause with those seeking to
undermine or replace public institutions or with critics who delight
in reviling those whose task it is to teach and administer in public
schools.
Indeed, narratives suggesting that the ‘sky is falling’ tend to be, in
our view, grounded in fantasies about what public schools, or teaching
and learning, are or could be, as much as they are grounded in the
historical realities of public schools or the realities of so-called
privatization. This contention is not unrelated to the observation
that the liberal defense of public schools is most often undertaken by
those with economic, social and racial privilege ‘on behalf’ of the
variously disadvantaged, who may or may not share the same loyalty to
these institutions.
The author of the story describes the academy movement as ‘the razing
of state provision throughout the world. In the name of freedom,
public assets are being forcibly removed from popular control and
handed to unelected oligarchs’. In a related Guardian story, another
author suggests that it is the teachers, students and parents that
make a school what it is, not the authorities running it. Notable in
the British context is the emphasis again on local ‘community’ control
as an aspect of democracy, undone by the State and its corporate
clients. Schools are depicted as public goods, not private
commodities.
Is it not the least bit ironic that these people see individuals placed into ministries (without the permission or consultation of the public they claim to serve) as being "democratically selected?" People will decry corporate oligarchs, but they seem fine with those that were "voted in" (despite the fact that the election they were voted in from did not allow them to choose the best and most knowledgeable person for the Ministry of Education).
The liberal defense of real or imagined public schools, and its real
or imagined heritage, is not limited to the Anglo-American context.
The specific forms of this defense vary according to the particular
histories of state-provided education in different localities,
including the different purposes that citizens tend to believe are
best or necessarily fulfilled by their public schools. Public schools
in France and Japan are meant to instill loyalty to a shared French or
Japanese culture, so as to produce citizens respectively loyal to
France or Japan; American public schools are meant to provide
individual opportunity for social and economic advancement, to be the
engine of the fulfillment of the ‘American dream’; schools in most
countries – from Singapore to South Africa – are believed to promote
democratic citizenship, social cohesion, workers for the labor market
and so on. But these defenses also usually partake of a familiar set
of general propositions about what constitutes the public sphere
generally, and why schools in particular ought to embody certain
positive aspects of ‘publicness’. So in what does ‘publicness’
consist as this bears upon education?
Knight-Abowitz maintains that fair participation in shared governance
is the first requirement for public schools, something we understand
to mean that the issues entailed in decision-making should be
accessible to the relevant public, whose informed preferences and
opinions about how schools operate also should be taken under
advisement. But Knight-Abowitz admits that representative and
aggregative participation – the model in the United States of voting
for the local school board, for instance – has been largely a failure
with respect to engaging broad participation. A small percentage of
voters turn out for such elections, and those who represent either
majoritarian or special interests dominate school boards.
The structure that takes place in school boards also exists within private schools, so it's particularly interesting that people continually insist that these methods function (which rarely work anywhere and are often losing power, even if they manage to elect "progressive" people to them).
Private schools have "parent committees," and these things do very little because parents are not equipped (in terms of socialisation) to fight against schools... Even if that school is engaging in harmful behaviours that are hurting their own child. The entire structure, public or private, isn't as responsive as it claims to be.
These public institutions are also notoriously unresponsive to the
‘interference’ of the public, like parents. With the consolidation of
school districts over the past century, leading to districts
encompassing multiple communities and neighborhoods, the distance
between school boards and their constituents has grown. Knight-Abowitz
recommends a cure of deliberative democracy in which teachers,
parents, older students and other community members are encouraged to
create parallel governing structures. However attractive this remedy
might appear, it would seem to depend, in the end, on fantasies about
local communities and citizen organizations, and their possible
relationships to totalizing bureaucracies like the public school
system.
For the sake of legitimacy, public schools also must respect liberty
and pluralism. At a minimum, respecting liberty entails accommodating
a certain amount of choice with respect to parental and student
preference; respecting pluralism, too, would require that schools be
sufficiently diverse both in structure and organization in order to
accommodate a range of interests and needs. But Knight-Abowitz admits
that public schools do not and have not for the most part respected
either. Conflicting demands between majority and minority values
almost inevitably disadvantage minority students, despite laws that
attempt to ensure freedom of expression and nondiscrimination.
Her remedy is a ‘bi-focal’ view of school governance through which
competing demands might be negotiated. She suggests that the views of
the local majority can sometimes be trumped through consideration of
minority values, as well as through consideration of the law. But the
‘rights’ of minorities, in this view, must still be weighed against
the preferences of the majority. In any case, the preferences of the
majority – buttressed typically by politicians, school boards, school
administrators and the national culture itself – always structure the
everyday practices of public schooling. Neither ‘integration’ nor
‘value-neutral’ curricula have been sufficient to ensure consistent
respect for the nonstandard persons who populate public school
buildings: even when schools are almost completely segregated by
race/ethnicity/class, the controlling mindset informing educational
norms tends to be that of the dominant class, expressed through the
structures and administration of schooling, even when the children of
that class are permanently absent.
This pairs well, also, with the understanding that even "liberal-minded" or "progressive-minded" educators (or heads of schools) who still retain problematic understandings help perpetuate bigotries within schools.
For example, queermisic beliefs (particularly aimed at trans and non-binary individuals) can still perpetuate in a place that claims to be LGBTQIA+ supportive (because these spaces tend to lean heavily towards liberal understandings of queerness, which focus heavily on the cisgender LG side of things).
Similarly, there are certain bigotries that retain support within spaces that go overlooked by the head of school (or other teachers), especially when students are academically high achieving. This includes students who engage in misogyny, racism, etc but are seen as being "good people" because their grades and supposed effort in a course (two irrelevant factors) support them being "good students."
For Knight-Abowitz, equal opportunity is the third condition for the
political legitimacy of public schools. The ideal is perhaps most
commonly associated with public education and is meant to denote fair
access to a level playing field on which all children, irrespective of
ability or social standing, have a fair chance to receive an education
sufficient for personal success and social advancement. But if that is
the condition of legitimacy, the vast and persistent inequalities of
opportunity and outcome in schools across the world might then
indicate that public schools are not legitimate public institutions.
Knight-Abowitz lays blame for the admittedly pervasive inequality on
neoliberal policies that have decreased school funding and
redistributive practices generally and on propaganda that maintains
that poverty and discrimination are not more powerful than teachers in
accounting for achievement. The preferred solution is an increase in
tax revenues and higher investments in education, along with a return
to active desegregation and anti-poverty government action. But even
if one agrees with the critique of neoliberal divestment in public
education, and agrees that government might take a more active role in
relieving segregation and poverty, there is more than a little
wistfulness in forgetting that before there was the ‘new poverty’ of
neoliberalism there was an ‘old poverty’ and in most places even
deeper, with more overt inequalities.
The fourth pillar of democracy in public schooling would be full
attention to political education for democratic life. Knight-Abowitz
suggests that this would entail both curricular attention, across
disciplines, to the role of citizens in decision-making, and to the
creation of ‘democratic schools’ in which students and teachers could
actively practice democracy. The active promotion of democratic goals
in curricula and pedagogy tends to run up against the problems of
respecting liberty and plurality, but from the other direction. Many
parents, teachers and students take school to be the place where
individual goals of social and economic betterment can be pursued and
are not motivated to give their time to ‘political education for
democratic life’, which they tend not to see as promoting their own
interests. The fantasy here is that ‘citizenship education’ – however
valuable we might find it or however much we wish our own children
would receive it – is not a central feature of most public schools. In
fact, we would maintain that a very different kind of ‘citizenship
education’ – one inclining toward materialism and consumerism – is
very much part of the everyday life of schools and tends to lead to
the very kind of disengagement in public life that those at the top of
the field of education routinely lament.
Knight-Abowitz cites the professionalism of teachers as the fifth
component for the political legitimacy of public schools, normally
involving training and certification necessary for ensuring high
quality standards among staff. But professionalism of teachers has an
uncertain relationship with those ideal/imaginary aspects of public
education that are democracy-promoting. Many teacher educators are
ambivalent about promoting professionalism because it conflicts with
other beliefs about who teachers are and what they (ought to) do. On
the one hand, increased recognition of teachers as professionals seems
to legitimate teacher education itself, to constitute an argument for
better compensation, to increase the symbolic capital of teachers
generally, and probably to increase the learning and development of
students. Professionalization of teachers may also compete with the
‘expertise’ of local parents and community values, and potentially
erodes the possibilities for democratic community organizing based on
shared interests and status. Also, and perhaps more important, it is
arguably difficult to sustain the identity between the ‘professional
teacher’ (the expert, the technocrat) and the ‘caring teacher’ who
acts as a parental surrogate. The demand for professionalism also
conflicts with reluctance of citizens of education schools to
recognize differences between teachers, to acknowledge the existence
of a continuum of ability, motivation and competence among teachers,
even among themselves, at the top of the hierarchy of teachers. But if
the expertise of teacher educators does not ensure the professionalism
of teachers in public schools, then the struggle for status within the
Academy, always a losing proposition for the perennially marginalized
‘ed-school’, is further complicated.
I would also point out that there are a significant number of issues that arrived by requiring teacher certification. Some of which include nonsensical requirements within a hierarchy that should already recognise certain skills (e.g., literacy and numeracy tests that are required as part of someone's certification, despite the fact that the requirements to enter the program already infer the claimed "appropriate level" of literacy and numeracy); others include the fact that there is very little legitimate need for most school structures (and that being self-legitimising isn't a good enough reason to keep them), and the overwhelming majority of necessary skills could be handled through mentoring and community-based learning centers that promote and encourage self-directed learning (e.g., libraries in conjunction with print collectives and learning centers).
Everywhere there are enormous challenges in realizing the political
legitimacy of public schools, and this is no secret to educational
scholars and policy makers. Indeed, these phenomena are documented
year after year in dozens of countries and appear in hundreds of
publications, popular and academic, and the problems are usually the
same that were present at the historical beginnings of public
schooling.
This is particularly true if you read a lot of anarchist and socialist literature, as many of the same critiques that existed in the 1920s (for example) still exist today.
The systemic injustices of public schooling are what this
professoriate routinely and unapologetically teaches its students
about the history and theory of schooling. Nor should it be surprising
to said professoriate that increased and more justly distributed
funding, better teacher preparation and better teacher pay,
progressive curricula and pedagogy, democratic governance, cultural
inclusion, free lunch – all of which we would likewise embrace for our
own children and those of others – have not generally made
state-public schools less unsatisfactory than they are and have always
been for a large proportion of the students who attend them.
For the record, better "inclusion" of disabled students has yet to significantly improve outcomes for disabled students. (This is largely because of how difficult the accommodations are to acquire when a student needs them; they also aren't provided for any of the disabled adults who require them.)
It also hasn't made schools safer for a whole host of people, nor has it fully enabled integration of all people into the same spaces (e.g., if the "liberal" or "progressive" people where I live truly cared about all people having equal access to education, Roma and disabled children would not be segregated into different schools... yet, they still are).
Despite what appears to be consensus about the shortcomings of public
schools, those who declaim the ‘death of the public school’ appear not
to have learned the lessons they themselves have preached and continue
to advocate remedies that have been historically ineffective.
First, school systems are notoriously inefficient in distributing
financial resources to those most in need of help. Second, extra
funding may purchase specialized staff, new buildings, libraries and
computer labs but still leave disadvantaged children alienated from
learning if other resources are absent. Those resources will include
things like strong leadership, positive school climate, appropriate
discipline, nurturing teachers, a motivated peer group, involved
parents, role modeling, career guidance and consensus on academic
goals. Third, unequal resources, usually conceived exclusively as
unequal financing, goes to the very fabric of public education,
certainly in large countries where local control is paramount. But
irrespective of the country or the specific context, it is a truism
that local knowledge often is the best kind of knowledge for
addressing the needs of local school children. Part and parcel of this
favoring local control is to see ‘top-down’ approaches as anathema.
The distribution of funds has been interesting. Again, disability is one of the clearest ways to see how the "increased funding" doesn't necessarily lead to things like increased accessibility or appropriate accommodations. Not all disabled students require the same supports; this money is often provided with caveats explaining how it can be spent, and it often misses the supports that disabled students (and their families) state they need.
It also doesn't provide students who may suspect they have a developmental disability but not have "proof" in the form of a formal diagnosis (which also has a limited scope of recognition, as many children often go undiagnosed).
Inequalities, however, are not necessarily inequities.
The expansion of both the urban charter school movement in the United
States and the academy school movement in the United Kingdom has at
least in part been motivated by the insight that traditional
state-public schools are not effective in leveraging increased
resources to the benefit of the disadvantaged students they serve.
This is true. When the charter movement started, there were a number of progressives who saw them as an alternative that would actually function as ways to implement responsive learning environments.
But the whole thing has been co-opted (if not blatantly started by) right-wingers who wish to privatise everything.
Unfortunately, however, good teachers are not in abundance; indeed
most countries struggle with a significant teacher shortfall, and even
when there are enough teachers to go around, relatively few will be
above average. And, typically, it is a truism that schools serving
high concentrations of disadvantaged children are more likely to have
teachers with less experience and fewer qualifications.
Mostly true, yes. But what exactly is a "good teacher?" And it's worth also recognising that having qualifications does not inherently make you a good teacher.
One way to change this is to offer better teachers strong financial
incentives to work in schools with more challenging pupils.
"More challenging pupils" or children whose needs are going unmet within the school they're in?
On the other hand, in many circles to even broach criticisms of public
school teachers is tantamount to launching a full-on assault against
public education itself. Here, we encounter a myth about who or what
the ‘public school teacher’ actually is, namely, an autonomous,
student-centered agent. Contrary to this myth, teachers most often
serve as agents of the state, and as such are entrusted with carrying
out the aims of the state, which include using pre-selected course
materials, administering standardized tests, advising for class
placement and carrying out disciplinary procedures.
This is a criticism that I wish more people would be willing to broach. Conservatives are willing to engage in it, but they do so as a means to tear down learning institutions (regardless of what they are) that don't sit well with their traditionalist framework.
The left almost unanimously refuses to engage with it (except for anarchists and many socialists), refusing to recognise some of the key truths highlighted here.
Even those, like Darling-Hammond (2006, 2010), who champion teacher
education (reform) and enhanced teacher agency, as the main levers to
increasing public school success and legitimacy, are acutely aware of
the perennial shortcomings of traditional teacher education. But the
reforms that Darling-Hammond and others have managed to enact, built
on intensive assessment and model of the professional, that is
effective teacher tends to perpetuate the notion that teachers are and
must be ‘in control’ of their own classes, while simultaneously
subjecting teachers subject to the reformers’ hegemonic vision and
regulatory schemes. This may signal a return to an underlying message
of compliance that has been characteristic of teacher education for
the past century, rather than the dawn of new era of ‘agency’.
As someone who often struggles in any school system to work in the ways I see fit (e.g., actually trying to be the socially-constructed "belief" of the teacher -- a caring person who acts as a mentor in student learning), the underlying message of compliance is spot on.
The reason I struggle is not because of how my choices reflect upon the class and classroom management; it's because I am frequently told that my methods are "unorthodox" and "unappreciated."
Even when students tell me all that they've learned through those methods, even when I build good rapport with students (and families).
Doing anything against the traditional model (or the "appropriately adjusted for modern times" traditional model) leads your colleague-peers to question you.
Each succeeding year’s academic scholarship testifies again to the
lack of freedom and plurality, equal opportunity, shared
participation, democracy and professionalism – to return to
Knight-Abowitz’s list of legitimating factors – endemic to public
schooling. One might submit that most scholarly careers in education
have centered around documenting these daily features of public school
life, where those who have documented the failures of public schools
are the most keen to circle the wagons against any perceived threat to
the institution of public schooling itself.
There are a couple specific education podcast hosts who I feel fit this description almost perfectly.
For instance, it could be the case that we simply have an instance of
the insider-outsider dynamic, where it is perfectly acceptable to
complain and criticize one’s own system but not for others to do the
same.
Except...
There is something to this insider–outsider explanation, but it is
questionable whether the analogies work quite so well in the case of
public education. As we have argued, many of the criticisms of the
public education system come not from outsiders but rather from those
who are badly served by it. Indeed, many of the struggles to find
alternatives to what ‘the local public school’ has to offer one’s own
child have been launched by the marginalized and poor.
It could also be the case that one’s defense of the public school is
motivated by the concern to reform rather than to relinquish it to
the arbitrary machinations of the free market.
Except...
On the other hand, it is difficult to imagine the actors in any of
these scenarios being opposed to alternatives to the services that
they provide, let alone profound structural changes that may bring
about an entirely different way of more effectively providing those
services.
And a lot of teachers, administrators, and public school proponents are strongly against alternatives, claiming that any attempt to engaging in them is tantamount to destroying democracy.
The dominant model, as reformers willing to look inside as well as
outside the system point out, is of course one encompassing
legislation and massive investment from state governments, but also
politicians, academics, teachers, administrators and social workers
(to name but a few). And notice that all of these actors, to one
degree or another, are dependent upon this leviathan of a system and
hence are keenly (if unconsciously) invested in maintaining the status
quo.
Again, our aim here is not to repudiate the idea of a public as this
concerns important political ideals, or for that matter, essential
features of the education system. Instead, we remind the reader that
we are taking issue with the circle-the-wagons defense of ‘public
education’ against any and all criticisms. Indeed, the knee jerk
defense of ‘the public school’, and the concomitant fondness for what
never was, engages in a strange kind of disavowal, a psychological
rationalization that indefensibly reconciles what educational research
has been saying for nearly 50 years with what needs to happen to begin
to correct it. Taking always the ‘idealistic’ view (which again
incidentally opposes the history and theory commonly taught in
university education departments) in each case motivates liberal
advocates of the public school to reject all manner of reform as a
threat to ‘the public’. These views together represent a fantastical
take on the ‘public sphere’ sharply at variance with more critical
understandings. Moreover, to the extent that fanciful notions of this
public are rhetorically invoked as cures for what ails us now, in our
view these defenses merely exhibit bad faith, and as such approximate
Baldwin’s (2010, p. 103) more general observation about modes of
domination: ‘We have constructed a history which is a total lie, and
have persuaded ourselves that it is true’.
Additionally, we surmised the possibility that in this blindness,
there also was a kind of denial about how particularistic,
non-inclusive, coercive and unequal public schools are. In other
words, how is it that this knowledge of the real is so consistently
eclipsed by appeals to an ideal, or an imagined essence?
But the fact is that most contemporary defenders of the public school
do not seem so much interested in developing a normative theory of
public education – where the distance between the ideal and the real
can be explained sociologically, philosophically, economically or
through some other disciplinary logic – as they do in simply promoting
faith in a kind of transcendental, that is imaginary, institution.
This is something that I experience with so many people working in and around schools.
That is, an institutional actor imagines her world according to how
the institution presents itself, historically, rather than according
to how the institution actually functions, not to mention its effects
on society, on its own agents and on its clients, or students or
patients. To place this dynamic, as it relates to the individual,
within a properly psychoanalytic framework, we might speak of the
subject inclined to see herself in the reflection of the institution,
so that in order to avoid narcissistic injury the institution must be
imagined in such a way that the subject’s worth is preserved.
This definitely provides a better explanation for the kinds of interactions I've had with other teachers, some of whom acknowledge the issues of schools but then almost immediately dismiss them.
And with respect to the institution itself, representations of the
public school as democratic, liberty-enhancing, equitable,
participatory, democratic and professional – emanating from the
broader field of public education itself – are imaginary inasmuch as
they project what defenders of the public would like public schools
(and their own academic bastions) to be, rather than what public
schools in fact are.
These imaginary institutions are also self-representations, and the
sense of the integrity of the self for those within the field of the
public school depends on the ‘survival’ of this institution in its
imagined form. In everyday terms, people tend to see themselves as
mirror images of the institutions and organizations in which they have
invested not just their time and energy, but their sense of identity.
And this is also a part of why I divested from the 'identity' of teacher (inasmuch as I could, beyond the requirement to have a 'job title').
Denizens of this educational field – professors and teachers, who of
course themselves were once school-attending students – find
themselves now in a situation Bourdieu called hysteresis, when
dispositions are out of line with the field and with the ‘collective
expectations’ of its normality. In situations of crisis or sudden
change, especially those seen at the time of too-rapid movements in
social space, agents often have difficulty holding together the
dispositions associated with different states or stages, and some of
them, often those who were best adapted to the previous state of the
game, have difficulty in adjusting to the new established order.
Again, there are a few education podcasters who I can see this mirroring, but it's much larger than that.
But this also sounds identical to the kind of responses we've been seeing by so many officials, administrators, teachers, and families in response to schools during COVID. There is no attempt to adapt or change; it's all about maintaining the status quo, so this goes far beyond just the private/charter vs. public debate.